
Panpsychism, the
ancient doctrine that consciousness is universal, offers some lessons in how to
think about subjective experience today
For every inside there
is an outside, and for every outside there is an inside; though they are
different, they go together.
—Alan Watts, Man,
Nature, and the Nature of Man, 1991
I grew up in a devout
and practicing Roman Catholic family with Purzel, a fearless and high-energy
dachshund. He, as with all the other, much larger dogs that subsequently
accompanied me through life, showed plenty of affection, curiosity,
playfulness, aggression, anger, shame and fear. Yet my church teaches that
whereas animals, as God's creatures, ought to be treated well, they do not
possess an immortal soul. Only humans do. Even as a child, to me this belief
felt intuitively wrong. These gorgeous creatures had feelings, just like I did.
Why deny them? Why would God resurrect people but not dogs? This core Christian
belief in human exceptionalism did not make any sense to me. Whatever
consciousness and mind are and no matter how they relate to the brain and the
rest of the body, I felt that the same principle must hold for people and dogs
and, by extension, for other animals as well.
It was only later, at
university, that I became acquainted with Buddhism and its emphasis on the
universal nature of mind. Indeed, when I spent a week with His Holiness the
Dalai Lama earlier in 2013 [see “The Brain of Buddha,” Consciousness Redux;
Scientific American Mind, July/August 2013], I noted how often he talked about
the need to reduce the suffering of “all living beings” and not just “all
people.” My readings in philosophy brought me to panpsychism, the view that
mind (psyche) is found everywhere (pan). Panpsychism is one of the oldest of
all philosophical doctrines extant and was put forth by the ancient Greeks, in
particular Thales of Miletus and Plato. Philosopher Baruch Spinoza and
mathematician and universal genius Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, who laid down the
intellectual foundations for the Age of Enlightenment, argued for panpsychism,
as did philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer, father of American psychology William
James, and Jesuit paleontologist Teilhard de Chardin. It declined in popularity
with the rise of positivism in the 20th century.
As a natural scientist,
I find a version of panpsychism modified for the 21st century to be the single
most elegant and parsimonious explanation for the universe I find myself in.
There are three broad reasons why panpsychism is appealing to the modern mind.
We Are All Nature's
Children
The past two centuries
of scientific progress have made it difficult to sustain a belief in human
exceptionalism.
Consider my Bernese
mountain dog, Ruby, when she yelps, whines, gnaws at her paw, limps and then
comes to me, seeking aid: I infer that she is in pain because under similar
conditions I behave in similar ways (sans gnawing). Physiological measures of
pain confirm this inference—injured dogs, just like people, experience an
elevated heart rate and blood pressure and release stress hormones into their
bloodstream. I'm not saying that a dog's pain is exactly like human pain, but
dogs—as well as other animals—not only react to noxious stimuli but also
consciously experience pain.
All species—bees,
octopuses, ravens, crows, magpies, parrots, tuna, mice, whales, dogs, cats and
monkeys—are capable of sophisticated, learned, nonstereotyped behaviors that
would be associated with consciousness if a human were to carry out such
actions. Precursors of behaviors thought to be unique to people are found in
many species. For instance, bees are capable of recognizing specific faces from
photographs, can communicate the location and quality of food sources to their
sisters via the waggle dance, and can navigate complex mazes with the help of
cues they store in short-term memory (for instance, “after arriving at a fork,
take the exit marked by the color at the entrance”).
Bees can fly several
kilometers and return to their hive, a remarkable navigational performance. And
a scent blown into the hive can trigger a return to the site where the bees
previously encountered this odor. This type of associative memory was famously
described by Marcel Proust in À la Recherche du Temps Perdu. Other animals can
recognize themselves, know when their conspecifics observe them, and can lie
and cheat.
Some people point to
language and the associated benefits as being the unique defining feature of
consciousness. Conveniently, this viewpoint rules out all but one species, Homo
sapiens (which has an ineradicable desire to come out on top), as having
sentience. Yet there is little reason to deny consciousness to animals,
preverbal infants [see “The Conscious Infant,” Consciousness Redux; Scientific
American Mind, September/October 2013] or patients with severe aphasia, all of
whom are mute.
None other than Charles
Darwin, in the last book he published, in the year preceding his death, set out
to learn how far earthworms “acted consciously and how much mental power they
displayed.” Studying their feeding and sexual behaviors for several
decades—Darwin was after all a naturalist with uncanny powers of observation—he
concluded that there was no absolute threshold between lower and higher
animals, including humans, that assigned higher mental powers to one but not to
the other.
The nervous systems of
all these creatures are highly complex. Their constitutive proteins, genes,
synapses, cells and neuronal circuits are as sophisticated, variegated and
specialized as anything seen in the human brain. It is difficult to find
anything exceptional about the human brain. Even its size is not so special,
because elephants, dolphins and whales have bigger brains. Only an expert
neuroanatomist, armed with a microscope, can tell a grain-size piece of cortex
of a mouse from that of a monkey or a human. Biologists emphasize this
structural and behavioral continuity by distinguishing between nonhuman and
human animals. We are all nature's children.
Given the lack of a
clear and compelling Rubicon separating simple from complex animals and simple
from complex behaviors, the belief that only humans are capable of experiencing
anything consciously seems preposterous. A much more reasonable assumption is
that until proved otherwise, many, if not all, multicellular organisms
experience pain and pleasure and can see and hear the sights and sounds of
life. For brains that are smaller and less complex, the creatures' conscious experience
is very likely to be less nuanced, less differentiated and more elemental. Even
a worm has perhaps the vaguest sense of being alive. Of course, each species
has its own unique sensorium, matched to its ecological niche. Not every
creature has ears to hear and eyes to see. Yet all are capable of having at
least some subjective feelings.
The Austere Appeal of
Panpsychism
Taken literally,
panpsychism is the belief that everything is “enminded.” All of it. Whether it
is a brain, a tree, a rock or an electron. Everything that is physical also
possesses an interior mental aspect. One is objective—accessible to
everybody—and the other phenomenal—accessible only to the subject. That is the
sense of the quotation by British-born Buddhist scholar Alan Watts with which I
began this essay.
I will defend a
narrowed, more nuanced view: namely that any complex system, as defined below,
has the basic attributes of mind and has a minimal amount of consciousness in
the sense that it feels like something to be that system. If the system falls
apart, consciousness ceases to be; it doesn't feel like anything to be a broken
system. And the more complex the system, the larger the repertoire of conscious
states it can experience.
My subjective
experience (and yours, too, presumably), the Cartesian “I think, therefore I
am,” is an undeniable certainty, one strong enough to hold the weight of
philosophy. But from whence does this experience come? Materialists invoke
something they call emergentism to explain how consciousness can be absent in
simple nervous systems and emerge as their complexity increases. Consider the
wetness of water, its ability to maintain contact with surfaces. It is a
consequence of intermolecular interactions, notably hydrogen bonding among
nearby water molecules. One or two molecules of H2O are not wet, but put
gazillions together at the right temperature and pressure, and wetness emerges.
Or see how the laws of heredity emerge from the molecular properties of DNA,
RNA and proteins. By the same process, mind is supposed to arise out of
sufficiently complex brains.
Yet the mental is too
radically different for it to arise gradually from the physical. This emergence
of subjective feelings from physical stuff appears inconceivable and is at odds
with a basic precept of physical thinking, the Ur-conservation law—ex nihilo
nihil fit. So if there is nothing there in the first place, adding a little bit
more won't make something. If a small brain won't be able to feel pain, why
should a large brain be able to feel the god-awfulness of a throbbing
toothache? Why should adding some neurons give rise to this ineffable feeling?
The phenomenal hails from a kingdom other than the physical and is subject to
different laws. I see no way for the divide between unconscious and conscious
states to be bridged by bigger brains or more complex neurons.
A more principled
solution is to assume that consciousness is a basic feature of certain types of
so-called complex systems (defined in some universal, mathematical manner). And
that complex systems have sensation, whereas simple systems have none. This
reasoning is analogous to the arguments made by savants studying electrical
charge in the 18th century. Charge is not an emergent property of living
things, as originally thought when electricity was discovered in the twitching
muscles of frogs. There are no uncharged particles that in the aggregate
produce an electrical charge. Elementary particles either have some charge, or
they have none. Thus, an electron has one negative charge, a proton has one
positive charge and a photon, the carrier of light, has zero charge. As far as
chemistry and biology are concerned, charge is an intrinsic property of these
particles. Electrical charge does not emerge from noncharged matter. It is the
same, goes the logic, with consciousness. Consciousness comes with organized
chunks of matter. It is immanent in the organization of the system. It is a
property of complex entities and cannot be further reduced to the action of
more elementary properties. We have reached the ground floor of reductionism.
Yet, as traditionally
conceived, panpsychism suffers from two major flaws. One is known as the
problem of aggregates. Philosopher John Searle of the University of California,
Berkeley, expressed it recently: “Consciousness cannot spread over the universe
like a thin veneer of jam; there has to be a point where my consciousness ends
and yours begins.” Indeed, if consciousness is everywhere, why should it not
animate the iPhone, the Internet or the United States of America? Furthermore,
panpsychism does not explain why a healthy brain is conscious, whereas the same
brain, placed inside a blender and reduced to goo, would not be. That is, it
does not explain how aggregates combine to produce specific conscious experience.
Integrated Panpsychism
These century-old
arguments bring me to the conceptual framework of the integrated information
theory (IIT) of psychiatrist and neuroscientist Giulio Tononi of the University
of Wisconsin–Madison. It postulates that conscious experience is a fundamental
aspect of reality and is identical to a particular type of
information—integrated information. Consciousness depends on a physical
substrate but is not reducible to it. That is, my experience of seeing an
aquamarine blue is inexorably linked to my brain but is different from my
brain.
Any system that
possesses some nonzero amount of integrated information experiences something.
Let me repeat: any system that has even one bit of integrated information has a
very minute conscious experience.
IIT makes two
principled assumptions. First, conscious states are highly differentiated; they
are informationally very rich. You can be conscious of an uncountable number of
things. Think of all the frames from all the movies that you have ever seen or
that have ever been filmed or that will be filmed! Each frame, each view, is a
specific conscious percept.
Second, each such
experience is highly integrated. You cannot force yourself to see the world in
black and white; its color is an integrated part of your view. Whatever
information you are conscious of is wholly and completely presented to your
mind; it cannot be subdivided. Underlying this unity of consciousness is a
multitude of causal interactions among the relevant parts of your brain. If
parts of the brain become fragmented and balkanized, as occurs in deep sleep or
in anesthesia, consciousness fades.
To be conscious, then,
you need to be a single, integrated entity with a large repertoire of highly
differentiated states. Even if the hard disk on my laptop exceeds in capacity
my lifetime memories, none of its information is integrated. The family photos
on my Mac are not linked to one another. The computer does not know that the
boy in those pictures is my son as he matures from a toddler to an awkward
teenager and then a graceful adult. To my computer, all information is equally
meaningless, just a vast, random tapestry of 0s and 1s. Yet I derive meaning
from these images because my memories are heavily cross-linked. And the more
interconnected, the more meaningful they become.
These ideas can be
precisely expressed in the language of mathematics using notions from
information theory such as entropy. Given a particular brain, with its neurons
in a particular state—these neurons are firing while those ones are quiet—one
can precisely compute the extent to which this network is integrated. From this
calculation, the theory derives a single number, &PHgr; (pronounced “fi”)
[see “A Theory of Consciousness,” Consciousness Redux; Scientific American
Mind, July/August 2009]. Measured in bits, &PHgr; denotes the size of the
conscious repertoire associated with the network of causally interacting parts
being in one particular state. Think of &PHgr; as the synergy of the
system. The more integrated the system is, the more synergy it has and the more
conscious it is. If individual brain regions are too isolated from one another
or are interconnected at random, &PHgr; will be low. If the organism has
many neurons and is richly endowed with synaptic connections, &PHgr; will
be high. Basically, &PHgr; captures the quantity of consciousness. The
quality of any one experience—the way in which red feels different from blue
and a color is perceived differently from a tone—is conveyed by the informational
geometry associated with &PHgr;. The theory assigns to any one brain state
a shape, a crystal, in a fantastically high-dimensional qualia space. This
crystal is the system viewed from within. It is the voice in the head, the
light inside the skull. It is everything you will ever know of the world. It is
your only reality. It is the quiddity of experience. The dream of the lotus
eater, the mindfulness of the meditating monk and the agony of the cancer
patient all feel the way they do because of the shape of the distinct crystals
in a space of a trillion dimensions—truly a beatific vision. The water of
integrated information is turned into the wine of experience.
Integrated information
makes very specific predictions about which brain circuits are involved in
consciousness and which ones are peripheral players (even though they might
contain many more neurons, their anatomical wiring differs). The theory has
most recently been used to build a consciousness meter to assess, in a
quantitative manner, the extent to which anesthetized subjects or severely
brain-injured patients, such as Terri Schiavo, who died in Florida in 2005, are
truly not conscious or do have some conscious experiences but are unable to
signal their pain and discomfort to their loved ones [see “A Consciousness
Meter,” Consciousness Redux; Scientific American Mind, March/April 2013].
IIT addresses the
problem of aggregates by postulating that only “local maxima” of integrated
information exist (over elements and spatial and temporal scales): my consciousness,
your consciousness, but nothing in between. That is, every person living in the
U.S. is, self by self, conscious, but there is no superordinate consciousness
of the U.S. population as a whole.
Unlike classical
panpsychism, not all physical objects have a &PHgr; that is different from
zero. Only integrated systems do. A bunch of disconnected neurons in a dish, a
heap of sand, a galaxy of stars or a black hole—none of them are integrated.
They have no consciousness. They do not have mental properties.
Last, IIT does not
discriminate between squishy brains inside skulls and silicon circuits encased
in titanium. Provided that the causal relations among the circuit elements,
transistors and other logic gates give rise to integrated information, the
system will feel like something. Consider humankind's largest and most complex
artifact, the Internet. It consists of billions of computers linked together
using optical fibers and copper cables that rapidly instantiate specific
connections using ultrafast communication protocols. Each of these processors
in turn is made out of a few billion transistors. Taken as a whole, the
Internet has perhaps 1019 transistors, about the number of synapses in the
brains of 10,000 people. Thus, its sheer number of components exceeds that of
any one human brain. Whether or not the Internet today feels like something to
itself is completely speculative. Still, it is certainly conceivable.
When I talk and write
about panpsychism, I often encounter blank stares of incomprehension. Such a
belief violates people's strongly held intuition that sentience is something
only humans and a few closely related species possess. Yet our intuition also
fails when we are first told as kids that a whale is not a fish but a mammal or
that people on the other side of the planet do not fall off because they are
upside down. Panpsychism is an elegant explanation for the most basic of all
brute facts I encounter every morning on awakening: there is subjective
experience. Tononi's theory offers a scientific, constructive, predictive and
mathematically precise form of panpsychism for the 21st century. It is a
gigantic step in the final resolution of the ancient mind-body problem.
Further Reading
Panpsychism in the
West. David Skrbina. MIT Press, 2005.
Consciousness:
Confessions of a Romantic Reductionist. Christof Koch. MIT Press, 2012.
Integrated Information
Theory of Consciousness: An Updated Account. Giulio Tononi in Archives
Italiennes de Biologie, Vol. 150, No. 4, pages 293–329; December 2012.
No comments:
Post a Comment